Tuesday, January 27, 2015

Sometimes the Easy Thing is Also the Right Thing

This semester I'm taking a class called "Capital Punishment: Race, Poverty, and Disadvantage." It is shaping up to be a rather unsettling class, though obviously in ways that are a feature and not a bug. In any event, our reading for this week is Furman v. Georgia, the 1972 case in which the Court briefly declared the death penalty unconstitutional. This is what I like to call a "seriatim" case, one in which every single Justice wrote an opinion of his own (in addition to a per curiam announcing the judgment of the Court but not the reasoning); the word is used to describe the British practice, also followed during the first decade of our Constitution, in which there was no single opinion of the Court and each judge would always deliver his own opinion. Chief Justice John Marshall abolished seriatim decision-making to promote Court solidarity and enhance its power and prestige, but every so often (especially during the Burger Court, I've found) things break down and most or all of the Justices need to have their say.

Anyway, one of the opinions was of course by Justice Blackmun. Here's how it opened:
Cases such as these provide for me an excruciating agony of the spirit. I yield to no one in the depth of my distaste, antipathy, and, indeed, abhorrence, for the death penalty, with all its aspects of physical distress and fear and of moral judgment exercised by finite minds. That distaste is buttressed by a belief that capital punishment serves no useful purpose that can be demonstrated. For me, it violates childhood’s training and life’s experiences, and is not compatible with the philosophical convictions I have been able to develop. It is antagonistic to any sense of “reverence for life.”
This was a dissenting opinion. Because, Blackmun says, his sentiments against the death penalty are purely those that should characterize legislative or perhaps executive decision-making, not the judicial disposition of cases. A little later on he says that:
To reverse the judgments in these cases is, of course, the easy choice. It is easier to strike the balance in favor of life and against death.
The implication is that, while it would be easy, it would not be correct, and it would not be correct because this is not a decision for judges to make. This is a pretty common trope, employed perhaps most often by Justice Felix Frankfurter, although Blackmun's opinion is unusual in a way. The typical Frankfurter line is that "whatever we may think of the merits of this policy," it is not unconstitutional and therefore the judiciary is powerless to stop it. Blackmun, on the other hand, tells us in no uncertain terms what he thinks of the policy; he goes into considerable depth about how it is contrary to all of his deepest values.  Blackmun closed by saying that:
Although personally I may rejoice at the Court’s result, I find it difficult to accept or to justify as a matter of history, of law, or of constitutional pronouncement. I fear the Court has overstepped. It has sought and has achieved an end.
Of course, some several decades later Blackmun famously declared that he would "no longer tinker with the machinery of death." That is to say, he had become convinced not that capital punishment was inherently unconstitutional but that it could not be imposed through a system that was anything other than arbitrary and capricious, contrary to the Constitution's requirements.

There's a lesson in that, I think. From his childhood through his retirement from the Court and his death, Harry Blackmun felt nothing but revulsion toward the death penalty. When he joined the Court, he felt however compelled to ignore his own moral impulses and instead apply "the law," operating of course under the assumption that those were two disjoint categories. Justice Blackmun would not do the "easy" thing and strike down those laws he found so morally repugnant; no, he would follow the law. But the older, wiser Justice Blackmun eventually became convinced that the "hard" thing simply could not be done lawfully. He never took the position Justice Brennan forcefully (and, in my opinion, masterfully) espoused in Furman, that death was an inherently unconstitutional punishment. Rather he realized that judicial attempts to craft a system of procedural safeguards that would cabin the evils of the punishment, to "tinker with the machinery of death," were futile, that the system could never be good enough. That was the voice of experience, not naive idealism. It was rather naive when he once thought that such tinkering was worthwhile, that we could in fact build a good enough machine of death.* Experience taught him to follow his heart.

Yes, it is easy to strike the balance in favor of life and against death. There's a reason for that, and it's not just that it's the right thing to do, morally speaking (though it does follow from this basic fact). It's because a wrongful decision striking down these laws would have been no worse than any other decision wrongly denying legislative authority to the American people on some purported constitutional grounds, while a wrongful decision upholding them would have been far worse than any other decision wrongly permitting to them such legislative power, for it would have led the American government to kill people, human beings in its custody, in violation of the Constitution--perhaps the worst legal atrocity imaginable. Therefore, had I been in Blackmun's situation, I would not have voted to uphold the death penalty unless I was absolutely convinced that there was no possible legitimate constitutional argument for striking them down. This is ultimately the key point of Philip Bobbitt's theory of constitutional law: that the law is ultimately indeterminate, that there are different ways of making valid legal arguments and that these modalities can conflict, and that this is an acceptable, nay, indispensable part of our legal system because it allows us to choose. And that choice, between different possible legitimate ways of resolving a case, cannot help but be a place where conscience enters the legal system. For Bobbitt, this is the whole point.

In 1972, Harry Blackmun thought he didn't have a choice--or rather, he thought he had one choice that was easy and another one that was correct. But, fortunately, we live in a constitutional system that does make some room for conscience and for moral choice. And when we make those moral choices, when we follow our conscience in choosing between two visions of the law, of course those choices will feel easy. It should always feel easier to follow conscience than to disregard it. But just because it is easy doesn't mean it isn't also right.

Just ask Justice Blackmun.


*No, not that kind.

Tuesday, January 6, 2015

For the Record

Mike Piazza made his MLB debut in 1992, and played in 1912 games until his retirement after the 2007 season. Over his 7745 plate appearances, he had 2127 hits, including 344 doubles and 427 home runs, and drew 759 walks against 1113 strikeouts, good for a batting line of .308/.377/.545. That gives him a wRC+ of 140. He drove in 1335 runs and scored 1048. Piazza was a catcher for at least part of 1630 of those games, 1602 of which as the starting catcher (the rest of his time split between first base and the designated hitter role), and while his 23% caught stealing mark was well below the league average of 31% and he wasn't the world's best pitch-blocker either, he is thought to have been one of the best catchers at history in framing pitches to produce extra called strikes, and his pitchers loved throwing to him. Add it all up and Piazza was worth 59.4 bWAR and 63.5 fWAR, the sixth- and fifth-highest marks all-time for a catcher, respectively (in both cases virtually tied with Yogi Berra). Versus a more stringent baseline, Piazza put up 35.7 bWAA and 38.4 fWAA*, and during the productive portion of his career, from 1993 through 2003, he accumulated 38 bWAA and 41.2 fWAA. Piazza also hit .242/.301/.458 over 133 post-season plate appearances, hitting six home runs and eight doubles and racking up 15 RBIs and 14 runs scored, and leading the New York Mets to the 2000 World Series with a monstrous .412/.545/.941 batting line in the NLCS and put up a .636 slugging percentage against the Yankees. Earlier today, in his third year on the ballot, Piazza received votes from 69.9% of Hall of Fame voters, just shy of the 75% necessary for enshrinement.

Craig Biggio made his MLB debut in 1988, and played in 2850 games until his retirement after the 2007 season. Over his 12504 plate appearances, he had 3060 hits, including 668 doubles and 291 home runs, and drew 1160 walks against 1753 strikeouts, good for a batting line of .281/.363/.433. That give shim a wRC+ of 115. He drove in 1175 runs and scored 1844. He also stole 414 bases, and was caught stealing 124 times. Like Piazza he came up as a catcher and caught in 428 games, but moved off the position. Biggio spent 363 games in the outfield but the vast bulk of his time at second base, appearing there in 1989 games. Though he won four Gold Gloves at second base from 1994 through 1997, available defensive metrics view him as having been mediocre at every position he played. Add it all up and Biggio was worth 65.1 WAR (per both sources), the twelfth- and tenth-highest totals for a second baseman ever, respectively. He accrued 28.7 bWAA and 24.3 fWAA, and during the productive portion of his career, from 1989 through 2001, he accumulated 35.6 bWAA and 30.0 fWAA. He also hit .234/.295/.323 over 185 post-season plate appearances, hitting two home runs and nine doubles with 11 RBIs and 23 runs scored, and was part of the 2005 Houston Astros team that made it to the World Series. (Biggio hit .295/.343/.377 in that post-season.) Earlier today, in his third year on the ballot, Biggio received the votes of 82.7% of the voters, and will therefore be inducted into the Hall of Fame later this year.

Mike Piazza was a better baseball player than Craig Biggio. This is, I think, incontrovertible. Piazza was the undisputed best-hitting catcher of all time. Biggio was a decent hitter and a decent baserunner, and maybe a decent fielder if we believe the people voting on Gold Gloves (though not if we believe the admittedly fairly primitive defensive metrics--in fact, both FanGraphs and Baseball-Reference have Biggio with more negative defensive value at his positions, and at less valuable positions), but nothing special in any regard. But Biggio wasn't a catcher (or at least, unlike Piazza, he had to stop being one early in his career), and so he played a lot more games than Piazza and stuck around long enough after he was still good to get 3000 hits. Also, because he wasn't renowned for his power, he manages to escape the pall of the Steroid Era, which Piazza apparently doesn't despite the abject lack of anything remotely resembling evidence that he cheated. There is a cogent argument that Craig Biggio should not be a Hall of Famer. There is no cogent argument that Mike Piazza should not be a Hall of Famer. For at least a year, Biggio but not Piazza will be in the Hall. That's absurd, and the writers had better not make the travesty last any further years.

Piazza 2016!



*FanGraphs does not actually give a Wins Above Average statistic, but it gives Runs Above Average statistics for the four major components of WAR (hitting, baserunning, fielding, and position), and I calculated the listed figures from those.